Results for 'Myles I. Friedman'

962 found
Order:
  1.  9
    The psychology of human control: a general theory of purposeful behavior.Myles I. Friedman - 1991 - New York: Praeger. Edited by George H. Lackey.
    Searching for an explanation to human superiority, Friedman and Lackey offer their General Theory of Purposeful Behavior: People seek control as an end in itself--the ability to make accurate predictions is the means to that end. This tight knit theory defines the dynamic relationship between and among predictive processes responsible for human control and success. A distinctly different view of intelligence, this volume includes discussions on "Human Motivation", "Gaining Control", "Maximizing Control", and "Impediments to Control". Important implications of the (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  2.  60
    Events: A Metaphysical Study.Myles Brand - 1989 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 49 (3):525-529.
    I EXISTENTIAL PROOFS INTRODUCTION Metaphysical problems, like all philosophical problems, arise from a sense of puzzlement. What is puzzling is that the ...
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   30 citations  
  3. Plato on Why Mathematics is Good for the Soul.Myles Burnyeat - 1996 - In British Academy, 1995 Lectures and Memoirs. Oxford University Press USA. pp. 1-81.
    Anyone who has read Plato’s Republic knows it has a lot to say about mathematics. But why? I shall not be satisfied with the answer that the future rulers of the ideal city are to be educated in mathematics, so Plato is bound to give some space to the subject. I want to know why the rulers are to be educated in mathematics. More pointedly, why are they required to study so much mathematics, for so long?
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   46 citations  
  4. De Anima II 5.Myles F. Burnyeat - 2002 - Phronesis 47 (1):28 - 90.
    This is a close scrutiny of "De Anima II 5", led by two questions. First, what can be learned from so long and intricate a discussion about the neglected problem of how to read an Aristotelian chapter? Second, what can the chapter, properly read, teach us about some widely debated issues in Aristotle's theory of perception? I argue that it refutes two claims defended by Martha Nussbaum, Hilary Putnam, and Richard Sorabji: (i) that when Aristotle speaks of the perceiver becoming (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   33 citations  
  5.  13
    Broadening the Ecclesiocentric Claim.Myles Werntz - 2019 - Journal of the Society of Christian Ethics 39 (2):303-318.
    Much discussion surrounding Christian nonviolence in the late twentieth century has centered around the ecclesiocentric version popularized by Stanley Hauerwas. In this essay, I assess the manner in which virtue is connected to internal church practices for Hauerwas, such that displaying nonviolence external to the church risks losing the formative nature of church life. Using examples from contemporary proponents, I argue that when internal church practices, such as prayer, economic sharing, and interpersonal reconciliation are performed publically, they form their practitioners (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  6. Εικωσ μυθοσ.Myles Burnyeat - 2005 - Rhizai. A Journal for Ancient Philosophy and Science 2:143-165.
    The key phrase eikōs muthos is standardly translated ‘a likely tale’, suggesting an empiricist philosophy of science quite alien to Plato’s outlook. I argue for translating, in the first instance, ‘a reasonable myth’, and focus on the point that the reason involved in world-making is practical, not theoretical. This should make a significant differenceto how we assess the Demiurgic arguments reported to us in the dialogue.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
  7.  25
    Postcarbon Amnesia: Toward a Recognition of Racial Grief in Renewable Energy Futures.Myles Lennon - 2020 - Science, Technology, and Human Values 45 (5):934-962.
    Climate justice activists envision a “postcarbon” future that not only transforms energy infrastructures but also redresses the fossil fuel economy’s long-standing racial inequalities. Yet this anti-racist rebranding of the “zero emissions” telos does not tend to the racial grief that’s foundational to white supremacy. Accordingly, I ask: can we address racial oppression through a “just transition” to a “postcarbon” moment? In response, I connect today’s postcarbon imaginary with yesterday’s postcolonial imaginary. Drawing from research on US-based climate activism, I explore how (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  8. Why Doctors Hate Medical Ethics.Myles N. Sheehan - 1994 - Cambridge Quarterly of Healthcare Ethics 3 (2):289.
    For the past 3 years, since acquiring formal training in healthcare ethics and philosophy, I have been one of those physicians who “does” ethics. I teach medical students and residents, write articles, speak at conferences, chair an ethics committee, and informally consult with colleagues on cases where they request advice related to ethical issues in the care of patients. These activities have been a rewarding and challenging part of my practice. There has also been a fair amount of frustration. Unfortunately, (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  9.  15
    Quality Assured Science: Managerialism in Forensic Biology.Myles Leslie - 2010 - Science, Technology, and Human Values 35 (3):283-306.
    This article takes as its point of departure the idea that the adoption of managerial principles to ensure the quality of DNA evidence is an accident of history which has changed the ways forensic biology is conducted and forensic biologists think. I begin by defining managerialism and tracking its entry into the contentious world of forensic biology, asking how it is that a focus on efficiency and precise process control is affecting these labs. My analysis unfolds in two parts. I (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  10.  19
    Terrorism and the Peace of Christ.Myles Werntz - 2016 - Philosophia Christi 18 (1):109-117.
    Christian pacifism has often been construed as quietist and unconcerned with public order. By using the trifold categories of ad bellum, in bello, and post bellum used by just war theorists, I offer an account of how Christian pacifists might have a more full and active witness to the peace of Christ in times of conflict without abandoning their core convictions.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  11. Hornsby on Trying.Myles Brand - 1995 - Journal of Philosophical Research 20:541-547.
    In “Reasons for Trying” (JPR, 1995), Jennifer Homsby rejects several views about trying, including the volitional account, which identifies trying with an ‘inner’ uniform mental occurrence leading to action and the instrumental view, which explicates trying as doing one thing in order to accomplish something else. She proffers, rather, an explication, which I label ‘the capacity view,’ that identifies trying with the agent doing all that she can to accomplish the goal. In this note, I argue, first, that Hornsby’s approach (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  12.  12
    Friedman's Revenge: The Reform of “Liberal” Welfare States in Canada and the United States.Paul Pierson & John Myles - 1997 - Politics and Society 25 (4):443-472.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  13. Beiträge zur Philosophie von Stephan Körner.Myles Brand - 1983 - Grazer Philosophische Studien 20 (1):241-264.
    This paper recommends a framework for explaining largescale, complex actions. Philosophers have concentrated on simple actions — on hand raisings — far too long. Large-scale actions are the normal objects of legal and moral responsibility, as well as the kmd of activity for which the question of freedom is most pertinent. I focus on that part of the causal sequence constituting an action that begins after the decision and continues through the bodily movements: I call this part of the sequence (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  14.  17
    On decision-theoretic foundations for defaults.Ronen I. Brafman & Nir Friedman - 2001 - Artificial Intelligence 133 (1-2):1-33.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  15.  32
    C. S. Lewis – On the Christ of a Religious Economy – I. Creation and Sub‐Creation. By P. H. Brazier . Foreword by Judith Wolfe . Pp. xx, 298, Eugene, Pickwick Publications, 2013, £23.00. [REVIEW]Myles Hannan - 2015 - Heythrop Journal 56 (2):350-351.
  16.  8
    Can War be Just in the 21st Century? Ethicists Engage the Tradition ed. by Tobias Winright, Laurie Johnston. [REVIEW]Myles Werntz - 2016 - Journal of the Society of Christian Ethics 36 (2):222-223.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:Reviewed by:Can War Be Just in the 21st Century? Ethicists Engage the Tradition ed. by Tobias Winright, Laurie JohnstonMyles WerntzCan War Be Just in the 21st Century? Ethicists Engage the Tradition Edited by Tobias Winright and Laurie Johnston Maryknoll, NY: Orbis, 2015. 201 PP. + XXVII. $36.00One of the most common complaints surrounding the just war tradition is, ironically, the antiquity of many of its arguments. The tradition has (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  17.  10
    Delving into depth: an empirical investigation of the ordinary concepts of depth and profundity.Florian Cova, Céline Schöpfer & Morgane Myling Bezat - 2024 - Synthese 204 (5):1-35.
    We sometimes say about certain things (such as philosophical questions) that they are ‘deep’ or ‘profound’. But what does it mean exactly? Surprisingly, philosophers have been quite silent on this topic and there is neither consensual nor prominent conceptual analysis of ‘depth’. After surveying different proposals that have tried to capture depth in terms of explanatory depth, subject matter, emotional impact, understanding or complexity, we present the results of three studies in which we combine qualitative and quantitative methods to investigate (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  18. Carnap's Tolerance and Friedman's Revenge.Noah Friedman-Biglin - 2015 - In Pavel Arazim & Michal Dancak, The Logica Yearbook 2014. College Publications. pp. 109 -- 125.
    In this paper, I defend Rudolf Carnap's Principle of Tolerance from an accusation, due to Michael Friedman, that it is self-defeating by prejudicing any debate towards the logically stronger theory. In particular, Friedman attempts to show that Carnap's reconstruction of the debate between classicists and intuitionists over the foundations of mathematics in his book The Logical Syntax of Language, is biased towards the classical standpoint since the metalanguage he constructs to adjudicate between the rival positions is fully classical. (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  19. Suspended judgment.Jane Friedman - 2013 - Philosophical Studies 162 (2):165-181.
    Abstract In this paper I undertake an in-depth examination of an oft mentioned but rarely expounded upon state: suspended judgment. While traditional epistemology is sometimes characterized as presenting a “yes or no” picture of its central attitudes, in fact many of these epistemologists want to say that there is a third option: subjects can also suspend judgment. Discussions of suspension are mostly brief and have been less than clear on a number of issues, in particular whether this third option should (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   206 citations  
  20.  49
    Reply to Flage's On Friedman's Look.Lesley Friedman - 1993 - Hume Studies 19 (1):199-202.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:Reply to Flage Lesley Friedman "The chiefexercise of the memory," Hume tells us, "is not to preserve the simple ideas, but their order and position."1 On Daniel Flage's interpretation ofHume, however, it is the only exercise ofthe memory (1985a, 1985b, 1990). Flage's account can accommodate onlymemories of complex ideas; he disallows the possibility of 'preserving* a simple idea in its simplicity. Yet there is an example of a (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  21. Why Suspend Judging?Jane Friedman - 2017 - Noûs 51 (2):302-326.
    In this paper I argue that suspension of judgment is intimately tied to inquiry and in particular that one is suspending judgment about some question if and only if one is inquiring into that question.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   190 citations  
  22. Inquiry and Belief.Jane Friedman - 2017 - Noûs 53 (2):296-315.
    In this paper I look at belief and degrees of belief through the lens of inquiry. I argue that belief and degrees of belief play different roles in inquiry. In particular I argue that belief is a “settling” attitude in a way that degrees of belief are not. Along the way I say more about what inquiring amounts to, argue for a central norm of inquiry connecting inquiry and belief and say more about just what it means to have an (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   158 citations  
  23.  60
    The physiological psychology of hunger: A physiological perspective.Mark I. Friedman & Edward M. Stricker - 1976 - Psychological Review 83 (6):409-431.
  24. Question‐directed attitudes.Jane Friedman - 2013 - Philosophical Perspectives 27 (1):145-174.
    In this paper I argue that there is a class of attitudes that have questions (rather than propositions or something else) as contents.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   134 citations  
  25. Intentions and Inquiry.Daniel C. Friedman - 2025 - Mind 134 (533):85-106.
    This paper defends the Intention Account of Inquiry. On this account, inquiry is best understood by appeal to a ‘question-directed intention’ (QDI), an intention to answer a question broadly construed. This account’s core commitments help meet recent challenges plaguing extant approaches to characterizing inquiry. First, QDIs are the type of mental state central to inquiry, not attitudes like curiosity or wonder. Second, holding a QDI towards a question and acting in service of it constitutes the start of inquiry. Third, controversial (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  26. Spinoza's problem of “other minds”.Joel I. Friedman - 1983 - Synthese 57 (1):99 - 126.
  27. Rational Agnosticism and Degrees of Belief.Jane Friedman - 2013 - Oxford Studies in Epistemology 4:57.
    There has been much discussion about whether traditional epistemology's doxastic attitudes are reducible to degrees of belief. In this paper I argue that what I call the Straightforward Reduction - the reduction of all three of believing p, disbelieving p, and suspending judgment about p, not-p to precise degrees of belief for p and not-p that ought to obey the standard axioms of the probability calculus - cannot succeed. By focusing on suspension of judgment (agnosticism) rather than belief, we can (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   58 citations  
  28. Junk Beliefs and Interest‐Driven Epistemology.Jane Friedman - 2017 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 97 (3):568-583.
    In this paper I revisit Gilbert Harman's arguments for a "clutter avoidance" norm. The norm -- which says that we ought to avoid cluttering our minds with trivialities -- is widely endorsed. I argue that it has some fairly dramatic consequences for normative epistemology.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   38 citations  
  29. Zetetic Epistemology.Jane Friedman - forthcoming - In Baron Reed & A. K. Flowerree, Towards an Expansive Epistemology: Norms, Action, and the Social Sphere. Routledge.
    In this paper I explore the contours of a picture of normative epistemology that speaks centrally to the question of how to inquire rather than just the question of what to believe. What if normative epistemology were expanded to encompass inquiry in full? I argue that while a 'zetetic epistemology' builds on traditional normative epistemology in many appealing ways, it also faces some challenges.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   29 citations  
  30.  38
    The Machinery of Freedom.David Friedman - unknown
    Capitalism is the best. It's free enterprise. Barter. Gimbels, if I get really rank with the clerk, 'Well I don't like this', how I can resolve it? If it really gets ridiculous, I go, 'Frig it, man, I walk.' What can this guy do at Gimbels, even if he was the president of Gimbels? He can always reject me from that store, but I can always go to Macy's. He can't really hurt me. Communism is like one big phone company. (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   79 citations  
  31. Kant on geometry and spatial intuition.Michael Friedman - 2012 - Synthese 186 (1):231-255.
    I use recent work on Kant and diagrammatic reasoning to develop a reconsideration of central aspects of Kant’s philosophy of geometry and its relation to spatial intuition. In particular, I reconsider in this light the relations between geometrical concepts and their schemata, and the relationship between pure and empirical intuition. I argue that diagrammatic interpretations of Kant’s theory of geometrical intuition can, at best, capture only part of what Kant’s conception involves and that, for example, they cannot explain why Kant (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   45 citations  
  32.  80
    (1 other version)Was Spinoza fooled by the ontological argument?Joel I. Friedman - 1982 - Philosophia 11 (3-4):307-344.
  33. The practice of partiality.Marilyn Friedman - 1991 - Ethics 101 (4):818-835.
    This essay counteracts that trend [regarding the debate about whether partiality can be justified, those supporting impartiality have generally been on the offensive arguing that morality calls for impartiality] by taking a closer look at the moral complexity of our social practices of partiality. My adoption of this approach does not represent an endorsement of current notions of impartiality. The ideal of impartiality, in my view, should be substantially reformulated. However, that the concept of partiality is transparently defensible. In this (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   35 citations  
  34.  81
    An overview of spinoza'sehics.Joel I. Friedman - 1978 - Synthese 37 (1):67 - 106.
  35. (2 other versions)Kant, Kuhn, and the rationality of science.Michael Friedman - 2002 - Philosophy of Science 69 (2):171-90.
    This paper considers the evolution of the problem of scientific rationality from Kant through Carnap to Kuhn. I argue for a relativized and historicized version of the original Kantian conception of scientific a priori principles and examine the way in which these principles change and develop across revolutionary paradigm shifts. The distinctively philosophical enterprise of reflecting upon and contextualizing such principles is then seen to play a key role in making possible rational intersubjective communication between otherwise incommensurable paradigms.
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   47 citations  
  36. Teleological epistemology.Jane Friedman - 2019 - Philosophical Studies 176 (3):673-691.
    It is typically thought that some epistemic states are valuable—knowing, truly or accurately believing, understanding. These are states it’s thought good to be in and it’s also said that we aim or want to be in them. It is then sometimes claimed that these sorts of thoughts about epistemic goods or values ground or explain our epistemic norms. For instance, we think subjects should follow their evidence when they form their beliefs. But why should they? Why not believe against the (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  37. Modal Platonism: an Easy Way to Avoid Ontological Commitment to Abstract Entities.Joel I. Friedman - 2005 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 34 (3):227-273.
    Modal Platonism utilizes "weak" logical possibility, such that it is logically possible there are abstract entities, and logically possible there are none. Modal Platonism also utilizes a non-indexical actuality operator. Modal Platonism is the EASY WAY, neither reductionist nor eliminativist, but embracing the Platonistic language of abstract entities while eliminating ontological commitment to them. Statement of Modal Platonism. Any consistent statement B ontologically committed to abstract entities may be replaced by an empirically equivalent modalization, MOD(B), not so ontologically committed. This (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  38. What Makes You So Sure? Dogmatism, Fundamentalism, Analytic Thinking, Perspective Taking and Moral Concern in the Religious and Nonreligious.Jared Friedman & Anthony I. Jack - 2017 - Journal of Religion and Health 57 (1):157–190.
    Better understanding the psychological factors related to certainty in one’s beliefs (i.e., dogmatism) has important consequences for both individuals and social groups. Generally, beliefs can find support from at least two different routes of information processing: social/moral considerations or analytic/empirical reasoning. Here, we investigate how these two psychological constructs relate to dogmatism in two groups of individuals who preferentially draw on the former or latter sort of information when forming beliefs about the world- religious and non religious individuals. Across two (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  39.  98
    A borel reducibility theory for classes of countable structures.Harvey Friedman & Lee Stanley - 1989 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 54 (3):894-914.
    We introduce a reducibility preordering between classes of countable structures, each class containing only structures of a given similarity type (which is allowed to vary from class to class). Though we sometimes work in a slightly larger context, we are principally concerned with the case where each class is an invariant Borel class (i.e. the class of all models, with underlying set $= \omega$, of an $L_{\omega_1\omega}$ sentence; from this point of view, the reducibility can be thought of as a (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   53 citations  
  40. Zetetic Rights and Wrong(ing)s.Daniel C. Friedman - forthcoming - Philosophical Quarterly.
    What do we owe those with whom we inquire? Presumably, quite a bit. Anything beyond what is necessary to secure knowledge? Yes. In this paper, I argue for a class of ‘zetetic rights.’ These are rights distinctive to participants in group inquiry. Zetetic rights help protect important central interests of inquirers. These include a right to aid, a right against interference, and a right to exert influence over the course of inquiry. Building on arguments by Fricker (2015), I defend these (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  41. Mapping Cognitive Structure onto the Landscape of Philosophical Debate: an Empirical Framework with Relevance to Problems of Consciousness, Free will and Ethics.Jared P. Friedman & Anthony I. Jack - 2018 - Review of Philosophy and Psychology 9 (1):73-113.
    There has been considerable debate in the literature as to whether work in experimental philosophy actually makes any significant contribution to philosophy. One stated view is that many X-Phi projects, notwithstanding their focus on topics relevant to philosophy, contribute little to philosophical thought. Instead, it has been claimed the contribution they make appears to be to cognitive science. In contrast to this view, here we argue that at least one approach to X-Phi makes a contribution which parallels, and also extends, (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  42. Carnap on theoretical terms: structuralism without metaphysics.Michael Friedman - 2011 - Synthese 180 (2):249 - 263.
    Both realists and instrumentalists have found it difficult to understand (much less accept) Carnap's developed view on theoretical terms, which attempts to stake out a neutral position between realism and instrumentalism. I argue that Carnap's mature conception of a scientific theory as the conjunction of its Ramsey sentence and Carnap sentence can indeed achieve this neutral position. To see this, however, we need to see why the Newman problem raised in the context of recent work on structural realism is no (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   20 citations  
  43. (1 other version)Kantian Themes in Contemporary Philosophy.Michael Friedman & Graham Bird - 1998 - Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 72 (1):111-129.
    [Michael Friedman] This paper considers the extent to which Kant's vision of a distinctively 'transcendental' task for philosophy is essentially tied to his views on the foundations of the mathematical and physical sciences. Contemporary philosophers with broadly Kantian sympathies have attempted to reinterpret his project so as to isolate a more general philosophical core not so closely tied to the details of now outmoded mathematical-physical theories (Euclidean geometry and Newtonian physics). I consider two such attempts, those of Strawson and (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  44.  68
    Beyond accountability for reasonableness.Alex Friedman - 2008 - Bioethics 22 (2):101–112.
    This paper is a critique of Norman Daniels' and James Sabin's ‘Accountability for Reasonableness’ framework for making priority-setting decisions in health care in the face of widespread disagreement about values. Accountability for Reasonableness has been rapidly gaining worldwide acceptance, arguably to the point of becoming the dominant paradigm in the field of health policy. The framework attempts to set ground rules for a procedure that ensures that whatever decisions result will be fair, reasonable, and legitimate to the extent that even (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   30 citations  
  45. Extending the Dynamics of Reason.Michael Friedman - 2011 - Erkenntnis 75 (3):431-444.
    What I call the dynamics of reason is a post-Kuhnian approach to the history and philosophy of science articulating a relativized and historicized version of the Kantian conception of the rationality and objectivity of the modern physical sciences. I here discuss two extensions of this approach. I argue that, although the relativized standards of rationality in question change over time, the particular way in which they do this still preserves the trans-historical rationality of the entire process. I also make a (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  46. Poincaré's conventionalism and the logical positivists.Michael Friedman - 1995 - Foundations of Science 1 (2):299-314.
    The logical positivists adopted Poincare's doctrine of the conventionality of geometry and made it a key part of their philosophical interpretation of relativity theory. I argue, however, that the positivists deeply misunderstood Poincare's doctrine. For Poincare's own conception was based on the group-theoretical picture of geometry expressed in the Helmholtz-Lie solution of the space problem, and also on a hierarchical picture of the sciences according to which geometry must be presupposed be any properly physical theory. But both of this pictures (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   22 citations  
  47.  52
    Taking ignorance seriously: Rejoinder to critics.Jeffrey Friedman - 2006 - Critical Review: A Journal of Politics and Society 18 (4):467-532.
    In “Popper, Weber, and Hayek,” I claimed that the economic and political world governed by social democracy is too complex to offer hope for rational social‐democratic policy making. I extrapolated this conclusion from the claim, made by Austrian‐school economists in the 1920s and 30s, that central economic planning would face insurmountable “knowledge problems.” Israel Kirzner's Reply indicates the need to keep the Austrians’ cognitivist argument conceptually distinct from more familiar incentives arguments, which can tacitly reintroduce the assumption of omniscience against (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   22 citations  
  48.  45
    The new consensus: I. The Fukuyama thesis.Jeffrey Friedman - 1989 - Critical Review: A Journal of Politics and Society 3 (3-4):373-410.
    Fukuyama's argument that we have recently reached ?The End of History?; is defended against writers who fail to appreciate the Hegelian meaning of Fukuyama's ?Endism,?; but is criticized for using simplistic dichotomies that evade the economic and ideological convergence of East and West. Against Fukuyama, the economic critique of socialism, revisionist scholarship on early Soviet economic history, and the history of the libertarian ideas of Rousseau, Kant, Hegel and Marx are deployed to show that history ?ended?; years ago: the creeds (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  49.  25
    Downey, R., Gasarch, W. and Moses, M., The structure.S. D. Friedman, W. G. Handley, S. S. Wainer, A. Joyal, I. Moerdijk, L. Newelski, F. van Engelen & J. van Oosten - 1994 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 70 (1):287.
  50.  62
    Plato'seuthyphro and Leibniz' law.Joel I. Friedman - 1982 - Philosophia 12 (1-2):1-20.
1 — 50 / 962